When pressed, the concept of [God as causa sui] soon shows itself incoherent and dogmatically
precarious. At a purely formal level, it seems to suggest that God in some way
precedes himself as his own cause . . . The dogmatic difficulties are equally
serious. Talk of God as his own cause cannot easily cohere with teaching about
divine eternity or immutability, since it appears to introduce an actualist
concept of God’s ‘coming-to-be’ as the result of some causal process. Further,
it imperils divine simplicity, introducing distinctions between cause and that
which is caused, or between potentiality and act, which, by attributing
potentiality to God, undermine the all-important identity of essence and
existence in God . . . By suggesting that God produces himself, it seems to
require the possibility of God’s non-existence as a kind of background to his
being. In effect, a God who is his own cause lacks an integral element of
perfection. If the concept of causa sui
is to be used, therefore, the notion of cause must first be stripped of any
associations with ‘becoming’ or ‘coming-into-existence’ – of anything that
might corrode the eternal fullness of God’s being.
You’ll forgive me for not being the most studious of Bible
scholars, but I thought I’d post a couple of observations I made today when
reading Acts 9:1-22 – today’s reading for the festival that is the Conversion
of Paul. And here’s Acts 9:1-9, from which my observations have come:
Meanwhile, Saul was
still spewing out murderous threats against the Lord’s disciples. He went to
the high priest, seeking letters to the synagogues in Damascus. If he found
persons who belonged to the Way, whether men or women, these letters would
authorize him to take them as prisoners to Jerusalem. During the journey, as he
approached Damascus, suddenly a light from heaven encircled him. He fell to the
ground and heard a voice asking him, “Saul, Saul, why are you harassing me?”
Saul asked, “Who are you, Lord?”
“I am Jesus, whom you are harassing,” came the reply. “Now get up and enter
the city. You will be told what you must do.”
Those traveling with him stood there speechless; they heard the voice but
saw no one. After they picked Saul up from the ground, he opened his eyes but
he couldn’t see. So they led him by the hand into Damascus. For three days he
was blind and neither ate nor drank anything.
First, there’s the commonplace observation that by
persecuting the believers, Saul is persecuting Jesus himself. But a parallel
passage flashed through my mind: Matthew 25:31-46, the so-called parable of the
sheep and goats. I subscribe to the view that ‘the least of these’ in Matthew
here is a reference to the Church, so that the sheep and the goats within the
parable are those who adopt different stances to the suffering people of Jesus.
My first observation, then, about the Acts 9 passage is nothing too profound –
it’s a simple recognition that the Church is included within the divine identity
in some way, and that there is a consistency of thought between Matthew 25 and
Acts 9.
My second observation might be obvious to some and strained
for others, but I couldn’t help but think of Jesus’s own death and resurrection
when the text states that Saul was blind for three days and consumed nothing.
If this reading isn’t too absurd or forced, then surely it’s possible to say that
Saul’s own experience mirrored Jesus’s Easter Saturday emptiness in some way
until he is ‘resurrected’ to new life as Paul the Apostle. Here, Saul himself
is included within the divine identity, within Jesus’s own sufferings – and so
the Church’s, too.
Those who are idle in the pursuit of righteousness count
theological terminology as secondary, together with attempts to search out the
hidden meaning in this phrase or that syllable, but those conscious of the goal
of our calling realize that we are to become like God, as far as this is
possible for human nature. But we cannot become like God unless we have
knowledge of Him, and without lessons there will be no knowledge. Instruction
begins with the proper use of speech, and syllables and words are the elements
of speech. Therefore to scrutinize syllables is not a superfluous task. Just
because certain questions seem insignificant is no reason to ignore them.
Hunting truth is no easy task; we must look everywhere for its tracks.
St Basil the Great, On the Holy Spirit, translated and with an introduction by David Anderson.
Poplar Patristics Series 5 (Crestwood, NT: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1980),
1.2, p. 16
Basil was referring specifically to the use of prepositions
in the doxology, but I think what he says about the need to press our theology
in service of the truth can be further extrapolated.
I’ve recently come across Hillsong’s ‘This I Believe (The Creed)’, written by Ben Fielding and Matt Crocker. We’ve sung it in the church
where I worship for the past two weeks in place of saying the Nicene Creed or
one of Common Worship’s so-called ‘Authorized Affirmations of Faith’. Needless to say, I have some reservations about the
Hillsong version, and not just because musically I find it trite (a friend also
says it reminds him of Peter Cetera’s ‘The Glory of Love’). I’m finding it hard
to articulate my reservations, so what follows is a little disorganized; but it’s
fair to say that I think that ‘This I Believe’ dehistoricizes and so depoliticizes
the Apostles’ Creed on which it’s (presumably) based. Here are the lyrics:
Our Father everlasting
The all-creating One
God Almighty
Through your Holy Spirit
Conceiving Christ the Son
Jesus our Saviour.
I believe in God our Father
I believe in Christ the Son
I believe in the Holy Spirit
Our God is three in one
I believe in the resurrection
That we will rise again
For I believe in the Name of Jesus.
Our Judge and our Defender
Suffered and crucified
Forgiveness is in you
Descended into darkness
You rose in glorious life
Forever seated high.
I believe in you
I believe you rose again
I believe that Jesus Christ is Lord.
I believe in life eternal
I believe in the virgin birth
I believe in the saints’ communion
And in your holy Church.
I believe in the resurrection
When Jesus comes again
For I believe in the Name of Jesus.
At first glance, there aren’t too many problems with the
words to ‘This I Believe’. All three persons of the Trinity are mentioned, and there
are references to the Son’s conception by the Holy Spirit, the virgin birth,
the Son’s crucifixion and suffering, the communion of saints, the Church, and
so on. But there are, I think, some significant omissions that present a dehistoricized
version of the Christian faith. So while there’s a reference in ‘This I Believe’
to the virgin birth, there’s no reference to Mary. And while there’s mention of
the Son’s suffering and crucifixion, there’s no mention of Pontius Pilate. But
why? The omission of Mary and Pilate from the Apostles’ Creed could encourage a
more mythical interpretation of the Son’s life rather than one that situates
him at a particular time and in a particular place. Moreover, there is no
explicit statement that Christ died and was buried. Of course, ‘crucified’
presumes death, but the lack of reference to Christ’s death and burial avoids
making a necessary connection with the reality of life and death in
first-century Palestine under Roman rule.
‘This I Believe’ also alters and embroiders the Apostles’
Creed. The Son (presumably) is described as ‘our Judge and our Defender’, but
this is ambiguous. Of whom is Jesus the Judge? Does the ‘our’ in ‘our Judge’
refer to every person in the world or to Christians alone? If the latter, then
arguably the geopolitical sovereignty of the risen and ascended Son is almost a
fiction. And why is Jesus described as ‘our Defender’? Again, is this a
reference to the whole world or just to Christians? If the latter, then how far
is this idea of Jesus as ‘our Defender’ no more than a belief in Jesus as a Big
Brother or a bodyguard, someone eager to protect Christians from the nasty bullies
or elements of the world?
Elsewhere in ‘This I Believe’, Jesus descended into darkness
– but not to the dead. ‘Darkness’ lacks the finality of ‘the dead’, perhaps,
and needn’t even mean ‘the dead’ (unless, of course, the songwriters are
channelling Old Testament conceptions of Sheol). There is a statement about
resurrection, but not necessarily resurrection of the body; a belief in the
holy Church, but not the holy catholic
Church; a recognition that ‘forgiveness is in you’, but no clear recognition
that this forgiveness is specifically the forgiveness of humanity’s sins; and
an acknowledgement that the Son is ‘forever seated high’, but not that he is
seated at the right hand of the Father, with all the geopolitical connotations
this conviction entails. And finally, is the phrase ‘You rose in glorious life
forever seated high’ a conflation of Christ’s resurrection and ascension, two
events in the life of Christ that the Apostles’ Creed itself takes care to
distinguish? This, alongside the line ‘I believe in the resurrection when Jesus comes again’, could express a
theology that sees salvation primarily as isolation and extraction from the
world.
All these things suggest to me that ‘This I Believe’ is a
dehistoricized version of the Apostles’ Creed. The tenets of belief have been
stripped of any clothes that might root them in a reality that doesn’t prioritize
the internal life of the individual believer. This means that ‘This I Believe’
is not only a dehistoricized version of the Apostles’ Creed, but a
depoliticized version, too. The affirmation that Christ is forever seated high
as ‘our Judge and our Defender’ is surely an impoverished view of the
sovereignty exercised by the risen Son as received by his Father, the
sovereignty to judge the living and the dead.
Now I’ll admit that many of these points may seem to be
stretching things a little. After all, if ‘This I Believe’ is simply based on the Apostles’ Creed, then it
probably doesn’t need to include every single detail contained within its
source. But here’s the thing: Any act of editing, including this song, is a process
of deciding what elements to leave in and what elements to leave out. Thus it’s
legitimate to ask why certain things have been ‘removed’ from the Apostles’
Creed – for example, Mary and Pilate, or Christ’s death and burial. I can’t say
for certain why Fielding and Crocker chose to write what they did; but my
concern is that, as it stands, ‘This I Believe’ is a dehistoricized and so
depoliticized version of the Apostles’ Creed. Why is this a problem? In my
view, a dehistoricized and depoliticized Apostles’ Creed is more amenable to
those whose faith is predominantly an individualized, internalized spirituality,
one focussed on salvation as extraction from the world rather than on salvation
as transformation of the world, and all expressed using terms sympathetic to a
theological therapeuticism.
How exactly
could God achieve infallible foreknowledge of every future event, including the
free actions of human persons? How could God exercise careful providence over
these same events? Byerly offers a novel response to these important questions
by contending that God exercises providence and achieves foreknowledge by
ordering the times.
The first
part of the book defends the importance of the above questions. After
characterizing the contemporary freedom–foreknowledge debate, Byerly argues
that it has focused too narrowly on a certain argument for theological
fatalism, which attempts to show that the existence of infallible divine
foreknowledge poses a unique threat to the existence of creaturely libertarian
freedom. Byerly contends, however, that bare existence of infallible divine
foreknowledge cannot threaten freedom in this way; at most, the mechanics
whereby this foreknowledge is achieved might so threaten human freedom.
In the
second part of the book, Byerly develops a model for understanding the mechanics
whereby infallible foreknowledge is achieved that would not threaten creaturely
libertarian freedom. According to the model, God infallibly foreknows every
future event because God has placed the times that constitute the history of
the world in primitive earlier-than relations to one another. After defending
the consistency of this model of the mechanics of divine foreknowledge with
creaturely libertarian freedom, the author applies it to divine providence more
generally. A novel defence of concurrentism is the result.
I’ve not read Byerly’s book yet, of course, but already I’m
wondering about how novel is his approach. It’s fine to contend that ‘God
exercises providence and achieves foreknowledge by ordering the times’, but I’m
not sure how this differs from many within mainstream Augustinian–Calvinist
traditions. I suppose much depends on what Byerly means by ‘primitive
earlier-than relations’.
The second book – Abraham’s Dice – is a volume edited by Karl W. Giberson:
Most of us believe everything happens for a reason. Whether
it is “God's will,” “karma,” or “fate,” we want to believe that an overarching
purpose undergirds everything, and that nothing in the world, especially a
disaster or tragedy, is a random, meaningless event.
Abraham’s Dice explores the interplay between chance
and randomness, as well as between providence and divine action in the
monotheistic religious traditions, looking at how their interaction has been
conceptualized as our understanding of the workings of nature has changed. This
lively historical conversation has generated intense and engaging theological
debates, and provocative responses from science: what of the history of our
universe, where chance and law have played out in complex ways? Or the
evolution of life, where random mutations have challenged attempts to find
purpose within evolution and convinced many that human beings are a “glorious
accident.” The enduring belief that everything happens for a reason is examined
through a conversation with major scholars, among them holders of prestigious
chairs at Oxford and Cambridge universities and the University of Basel, as
well as several Gifford lecturers, and two Templeton prize winners.
Now, as never before, confident scientific assertions that
the world embodies a profound contingency are challenging theological claims
that God acts providentially in the world. The random and meandering path of
evolution is widely used as an argument that God did not create life. Organized
historically, Abraham’s Dice provides a wide-ranging scientific,
theological, and biblical foundation to address the question of divine action
in a world shot through with contingency.
The contents of this one – found here – reveal quite a few
interesting-looking titles and some big-name contributors (e.g., Oliver Crisp,
John Hedley Brooke, and Alister McGrath). And I’ll be interested to see if any
fresh or alternative angles will be on view.
Here’s a cynical little ditty I’ve penned. It took about five
minutes to write (so don’t take it too seriously; it’s not exactly a masterly
critique of modern worship patterns) and is to be sung to the tune of Dave
Bilbrough’s 1983 classic, ‘I am a new creation’.
Towards the end of The
Faithful Creator, Ron Highfield outlines what he labels the ‘rhetorical
argument from evil’ against God’s existence:
The rhetorical argument from evil begins by rehearsing in
exquisite detail excruciating and nauseating accounts of horrendous cruelty and
suffering. It does not move to a conclusion by way of inference but ends with a
challenge, explicit or implicit: how dare you diminish the horror of human
suffering by making it a means to greater good or a higher harmony! Such
exclamations are more agonized protest than rational argument. It forces
believers to choose between shame-faced silence and playing the role of the
cold-hearted theodicist.
To elucidate the matter, Highfield looks at Voltaire’s Candide and Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov. Highfield’s
account of the latter is interesting because he notes how subsequent critics
focus on Ivan Karamazov’s rhetoric in ‘The Rebellion’ and ‘The Grand
Inquisitor’ and avoid the response that is the life of Elder Zosima. The point
is that the so-called rhetorical argument from evil cannot be refuted
intellectually; it can only be assuaged by recognising on an epistemic level that cruelty and suffering cannot be
explained away. We simply do not know why God allows rape or murder or
terrorism or exploitation to happen. But we can be sure, says Highfield, that
these things will not be for nothing: ‘To hope that God will “dry every tear”
does not imply that the tears were cried for nothing; rather it asserts that
life is stronger than death and joy more lasting than sadness.’ (p. 357)
I admit I’m not sure how far to go along with what Highfield
contends here. I have trouble accepting his distinction between metaphysical and epistemic absurdity (p. 356), because this implies that while we (currently)
may not know why something evil happens, we can be sure that that something
does have a proper place in God’s providence. How far does this stance simply
justify the presence of evil in a world created good? There is surely a
distinction to be made between saying that God works all things for good (Rom.
8:28) and that all things are justified or made acceptable by the good that
arises from them.
In this context of protest atheism, Highfield also offers a
critique of Jürgen Moltmann’s theology:
Moltmann explicitly denies that God is vulnerable to sin,
suffering and death by nature.
Instead, God voluntarily suffers so that the world might exist and God
voluntarily abandons the Son so that sinners might be accepted. But this theory
of divine self-limitation is a fiction; it is an all-too-convenient, ad hoc
hypothesis designed to secure the benefits of a finite and suffering God
without being burdened with its liabilities. If God can suffer willingly, it
follows that God’s nature is such that God can suffer, which is to say that God
is by nature vulnerable to suffering. Otherwise it would not even be possible
for God voluntarily to suffer. I can suffer and die. Hence I can suffer and die
willingly or unwillingly. If God can willingly suffer and die, does it not
follow that God can suffer and die unwillingly? (p. 359, emphasis original)
No; it doesn’t follow. Highfield is right to point out that
Moltmann’s theology means that God’s suffering entails an ability to suffer by nature, but this doesn’t mean that
God can suffer unwillingly. In the
end, then, while Highfield’s chapter on the rhetorical argument from evil is
fascinating and contains a number of insightful perspectives, I cannot help but
think the most appropriate response to such an argument is far simpler than he
makes out: genuine lament before God.